forked from owainwest/software-foundations
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
MoreInd.v
1158 lines (933 loc) · 42.6 KB
/
MoreInd.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(** * MoreInd: More on Induction *)
Require Export ProofObjects.
(* ##################################################### *)
(** * Induction Principles *)
(** This is a good point to pause and take a deeper look at induction
principles.
Every time we declare a new [Inductive] datatype, Coq
automatically generates and proves an _induction principle_
for this type.
The induction principle for a type [t] is called [t_ind]. Here is
the one for natural numbers: *)
Check nat_ind.
(* ===> nat_ind :
forall P : nat -> Prop,
P 0 ->
(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) ->
forall n : nat, P n *)
(** The [induction] tactic is a straightforward wrapper that, at
its core, simply performs [apply t_ind]. To see this more
clearly, let's experiment a little with using [apply nat_ind]
directly, instead of the [induction] tactic, to carry out some
proofs. Here, for example, is an alternate proof of a theorem
that we saw in the [Basics] chapter. *)
Theorem mult_0_r' : forall n:nat,
n * 0 = 0.
Proof.
apply nat_ind.
Case "O". reflexivity.
Case "S". simpl. intros n IHn. rewrite -> IHn.
reflexivity. Qed.
(** This proof is basically the same as the earlier one, but a
few minor differences are worth noting. First, in the induction
step of the proof (the ["S"] case), we have to do a little
bookkeeping manually (the [intros]) that [induction] does
automatically.
Second, we do not introduce [n] into the context before applying
[nat_ind] -- the conclusion of [nat_ind] is a quantified formula,
and [apply] needs this conclusion to exactly match the shape of
the goal state, including the quantifier. The [induction] tactic
works either with a variable in the context or a quantified
variable in the goal.
Third, the [apply] tactic automatically chooses variable names for
us (in the second subgoal, here), whereas [induction] lets us
specify (with the [as...] clause) what names should be used. The
automatic choice is actually a little unfortunate, since it
re-uses the name [n] for a variable that is different from the [n]
in the original theorem. This is why the [Case] annotation is
just [S] -- if we tried to write it out in the more explicit form
that we've been using for most proofs, we'd have to write [n = S
n], which doesn't make a lot of sense! All of these conveniences
make [induction] nicer to use in practice than applying induction
principles like [nat_ind] directly. But it is important to
realize that, modulo this little bit of bookkeeping, applying
[nat_ind] is what we are really doing. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (plus_one_r') *)
(** Complete this proof as we did [mult_0_r'] above, without using
the [induction] tactic. *)
Theorem plus_one_r' : forall n:nat,
n + 1 = S n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Coq generates induction principles for every datatype defined with
[Inductive], including those that aren't recursive. (Although
we don't need induction to prove properties of non-recursive
datatypes, the idea of an induction principle still makes sense
for them: it gives a way to prove that a property holds for all
values of the type.)
These generated principles follow a similar pattern. If we define a
type [t] with constructors [c1] ... [cn], Coq generates a theorem
with this shape:
t_ind :
forall P : t -> Prop,
... case for c1 ... ->
... case for c2 ... ->
...
... case for cn ... ->
forall n : t, P n
The specific shape of each case depends on the arguments to the
corresponding constructor. Before trying to write down a general
rule, let's look at some more examples. First, an example where
the constructors take no arguments: *)
Inductive yesno : Type :=
| yes : yesno
| no : yesno.
Check yesno_ind.
(* ===> yesno_ind : forall P : yesno -> Prop,
P yes ->
P no ->
forall y : yesno, P y *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (rgb) *)
(** Write out the induction principle that Coq will generate for the
following datatype. Write down your answer on paper or type it
into a comment, and then compare it with what Coq prints. *)
Inductive rgb : Type :=
| red : rgb
| green : rgb
| blue : rgb.
Check rgb_ind.
(** [] *)
(** Here's another example, this time with one of the constructors
taking some arguments. *)
Inductive natlist : Type :=
| nnil : natlist
| ncons : nat -> natlist -> natlist.
Check natlist_ind.
(* ===> (modulo a little variable renaming for clarity)
natlist_ind :
forall P : natlist -> Prop,
P nnil ->
(forall (n : nat) (l : natlist), P l -> P (ncons n l)) ->
forall n : natlist, P n *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (natlist1) *)
(** Suppose we had written the above definition a little
differently: *)
Inductive natlist1 : Type :=
| nnil1 : natlist1
| nsnoc1 : natlist1 -> nat -> natlist1.
(** Now what will the induction principle look like? *)
(** [] *)
(** From these examples, we can extract this general rule:
- The type declaration gives several constructors; each
corresponds to one clause of the induction principle.
- Each constructor [c] takes argument types [a1]...[an].
- Each [ai] can be either [t] (the datatype we are defining) or
some other type [s].
- The corresponding case of the induction principle
says (in English):
- "for all values [x1]...[xn] of types [a1]...[an], if [P]
holds for each of the inductive arguments (each [xi] of
type [t]), then [P] holds for [c x1 ... xn]".
*)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (byntree_ind) *)
(** Write out the induction principle that Coq will generate for the
following datatype. Write down your answer on paper or type it
into a comment, and then compare it with what Coq prints. *)
Inductive byntree : Type :=
| bempty : byntree
| bleaf : yesno -> byntree
| nbranch : yesno -> byntree -> byntree -> byntree.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (ex_set) *)
(** Here is an induction principle for an inductively defined
set.
ExSet_ind :
forall P : ExSet -> Prop,
(forall b : bool, P (con1 b)) ->
(forall (n : nat) (e : ExSet), P e -> P (con2 n e)) ->
forall e : ExSet, P e
Give an [Inductive] definition of [ExSet]: *)
Inductive ExSet : Type :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
(** [] *)
(** What about polymorphic datatypes?
The inductive definition of polymorphic lists
Inductive list (X:Type) : Type :=
| nil : list X
| cons : X -> list X -> list X.
is very similar to that of [natlist]. The main difference is
that, here, the whole definition is _parameterized_ on a set [X]:
that is, we are defining a _family_ of inductive types [list X],
one for each [X]. (Note that, wherever [list] appears in the body
of the declaration, it is always applied to the parameter [X].)
The induction principle is likewise parameterized on [X]:
list_ind :
forall (X : Type) (P : list X -> Prop),
P [] ->
(forall (x : X) (l : list X), P l -> P (x :: l)) ->
forall l : list X, P l
Note the wording here (and, accordingly, the form of [list_ind]):
The _whole_ induction principle is parameterized on [X]. That is,
[list_ind] can be thought of as a polymorphic function that, when
applied to a type [X], gives us back an induction principle
specialized to the type [list X]. *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (tree) *)
(** Write out the induction principle that Coq will generate for
the following datatype. Compare your answer with what Coq
prints. *)
Inductive tree (X:Type) : Type :=
| leaf : X -> tree X
| node : tree X -> tree X -> tree X.
Check tree_ind.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (mytype) *)
(** Find an inductive definition that gives rise to the
following induction principle:
mytype_ind :
forall (X : Type) (P : mytype X -> Prop),
(forall x : X, P (constr1 X x)) ->
(forall n : nat, P (constr2 X n)) ->
(forall m : mytype X, P m ->
forall n : nat, P (constr3 X m n)) ->
forall m : mytype X, P m
*)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (foo) *)
(** Find an inductive definition that gives rise to the
following induction principle:
foo_ind :
forall (X Y : Type) (P : foo X Y -> Prop),
(forall x : X, P (bar X Y x)) ->
(forall y : Y, P (baz X Y y)) ->
(forall f1 : nat -> foo X Y,
(forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (quux X Y f1)) ->
forall f2 : foo X Y, P f2
*)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (foo') *)
(** Consider the following inductive definition: *)
Inductive foo' (X:Type) : Type :=
| C1 : list X -> foo' X -> foo' X
| C2 : foo' X.
(** What induction principle will Coq generate for [foo']? Fill
in the blanks, then check your answer with Coq.)
foo'_ind :
forall (X : Type) (P : foo' X -> Prop),
(forall (l : list X) (f : foo' X),
_______________________ ->
_______________________ ) ->
___________________________________________ ->
forall f : foo' X, ________________________
*)
(** [] *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** ** Induction Hypotheses *)
(** Where does the phrase "induction hypothesis" fit into this story?
The induction principle for numbers
forall P : nat -> Prop,
P 0 ->
(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) ->
forall n : nat, P n
is a generic statement that holds for all propositions
[P] (strictly speaking, for all families of propositions [P]
indexed by a number [n]). Each time we use this principle, we
are choosing [P] to be a particular expression of type
[nat->Prop].
We can make the proof more explicit by giving this expression a
name. For example, instead of stating the theorem [mult_0_r] as
"[forall n, n * 0 = 0]," we can write it as "[forall n, P_m0r
n]", where [P_m0r] is defined as... *)
Definition P_m0r (n:nat) : Prop :=
n * 0 = 0.
(** ... or equivalently... *)
Definition P_m0r' : nat->Prop :=
fun n => n * 0 = 0.
(** Now when we do the proof it is easier to see where [P_m0r]
appears. *)
Theorem mult_0_r'' : forall n:nat,
P_m0r n.
Proof.
apply nat_ind.
Case "n = O". reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
(* Note the proof state at this point! *)
intros n IHn.
unfold P_m0r in IHn. unfold P_m0r. simpl. apply IHn. Qed.
(** This extra naming step isn't something that we'll do in
normal proofs, but it is useful to do it explicitly for an example
or two, because it allows us to see exactly what the induction
hypothesis is. If we prove [forall n, P_m0r n] by induction on
[n] (using either [induction] or [apply nat_ind]), we see that the
first subgoal requires us to prove [P_m0r 0] ("[P] holds for
zero"), while the second subgoal requires us to prove [forall n',
P_m0r n' -> P_m0r n' (S n')] (that is "[P] holds of [S n'] if it
holds of [n']" or, more elegantly, "[P] is preserved by [S]").
The _induction hypothesis_ is the premise of this latter
implication -- the assumption that [P] holds of [n'], which we are
allowed to use in proving that [P] holds for [S n']. *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** ** More on the [induction] Tactic *)
(** The [induction] tactic actually does even more low-level
bookkeeping for us than we discussed above.
Recall the informal statement of the induction principle for
natural numbers:
- If [P n] is some proposition involving a natural number n, and
we want to show that P holds for _all_ numbers n, we can
reason like this:
- show that [P O] holds
- show that, if [P n'] holds, then so does [P (S n')]
- conclude that [P n] holds for all n.
So, when we begin a proof with [intros n] and then [induction n],
we are first telling Coq to consider a _particular_ [n] (by
introducing it into the context) and then telling it to prove
something about _all_ numbers (by using induction).
What Coq actually does in this situation, internally, is to
"re-generalize" the variable we perform induction on. For
example, in our original proof that [plus] is associative...
*)
Theorem plus_assoc' : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof.
(* ...we first introduce all 3 variables into the context,
which amounts to saying "Consider an arbitrary [n], [m], and
[p]..." *)
intros n m p.
(* ...We now use the [induction] tactic to prove [P n] (that
is, [n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p]) for _all_ [n],
and hence also for the particular [n] that is in the context
at the moment. *)
induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = O". reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'".
(* In the second subgoal generated by [induction] -- the
"inductive step" -- we must prove that [P n'] implies
[P (S n')] for all [n']. The [induction] tactic
automatically introduces [n'] and [P n'] into the context
for us, leaving just [P (S n')] as the goal. *)
simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** It also works to apply [induction] to a variable that is
quantified in the goal. *)
Theorem plus_comm' : forall n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = O". intros m. rewrite -> plus_0_r. reflexivity.
Case "n = S n'". intros m. simpl. rewrite -> IHn'.
rewrite <- plus_n_Sm. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Note that [induction n] leaves [m] still bound in the goal --
i.e., what we are proving inductively is a statement beginning
with [forall m].
If we do [induction] on a variable that is quantified in the goal
_after_ some other quantifiers, the [induction] tactic will
automatically introduce the variables bound by these quantifiers
into the context. *)
Theorem plus_comm'' : forall n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
(* Let's do induction on [m] this time, instead of [n]... *)
induction m as [| m'].
Case "m = O". simpl. rewrite -> plus_0_r. reflexivity.
Case "m = S m'". simpl. rewrite <- IHm'.
rewrite <- plus_n_Sm. reflexivity. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (plus_explicit_prop) *)
(** Rewrite both [plus_assoc'] and [plus_comm'] and their proofs in
the same style as [mult_0_r''] above -- that is, for each theorem,
give an explicit [Definition] of the proposition being proved by
induction, and state the theorem and proof in terms of this
defined proposition. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** ** Generalizing Inductions. *)
(** One potentially confusing feature of the [induction] tactic is
that it happily lets you try to set up an induction over a term
that isn't sufficiently general. The net effect of this will be
do lose information (much as [destruct] can do), and leave
you unable to complete the proof. Here's an example: *)
Lemma one_not_beautiful_FAILED: ~ beautiful 1.
Proof.
intro H.
(* Just doing an [inversion] on [H] won't get us very far in the [b_sum]
case. (Try it!). So we'll need induction. A naive first attempt: *)
induction H.
(* But now, although we get four cases, as we would expect from
the definition of [beautiful], we lose all information about [H] ! *)
Abort.
(** The problem is that [induction] over a Prop only works properly over
completely general instances of the Prop, i.e. one in which all
the arguments are free (unconstrained) variables.
In this respect it behaves more
like [destruct] than like [inversion].
When you're tempted to do use [induction] like this, it is generally
an indication that you need to be proving something more general.
But in some cases, it suffices to pull out any concrete arguments
into separate equations, like this: *)
Lemma one_not_beautiful: forall n, n = 1 -> ~ beautiful n.
Proof.
intros n E H.
induction H as [| | | p q Hp IHp Hq IHq].
Case "b_0".
inversion E.
Case "b_3".
inversion E.
Case "b_5".
inversion E.
Case "b_sum".
(* the rest is a tedious case analysis *)
destruct p as [|p'].
SCase "p = 0".
destruct q as [|q'].
SSCase "q = 0".
inversion E.
SSCase "q = S q'".
apply IHq. apply E.
SCase "p = S p'".
destruct q as [|q'].
SSCase "q = 0".
apply IHp. rewrite plus_0_r in E. apply E.
SSCase "q = S q'".
simpl in E. inversion E. destruct p'. inversion H0. inversion H0.
Qed.
(** There's a handy [remember] tactic that can generate the second
proof state out of the original one. *)
Lemma one_not_beautiful': ~ beautiful 1.
Proof.
intros H.
remember 1 as n eqn:E.
(* now carry on as above *)
induction H.
Admitted.
(* ####################################################### *)
(** * Informal Proofs (Advanced) *)
(** Q: What is the relation between a formal proof of a proposition
[P] and an informal proof of the same proposition [P]?
A: The latter should _teach_ the reader how to produce the
former.
Q: How much detail is needed??
Unfortunately, There is no single right answer; rather, there is a
range of choices.
At one end of the spectrum, we can essentially give the reader the
whole formal proof (i.e., the informal proof amounts to just
transcribing the formal one into words). This gives the reader
the _ability_ to reproduce the formal one for themselves, but it
doesn't _teach_ them anything.
At the other end of the spectrum, we can say "The theorem is true
and you can figure out why for yourself if you think about it hard
enough." This is also not a good teaching strategy, because
usually writing the proof requires some deep insights into the
thing we're proving, and most readers will give up before they
rediscover all the same insights as we did.
In the middle is the golden mean -- a proof that includes all of
the essential insights (saving the reader the hard part of work
that we went through to find the proof in the first place) and
clear high-level suggestions for the more routine parts to save the
reader from spending too much time reconstructing these
parts (e.g., what the IH says and what must be shown in each case
of an inductive proof), but not so much detail that the main ideas
are obscured.
Another key point: if we're comparing a formal proof of a
proposition [P] and an informal proof of [P], the proposition [P]
doesn't change. That is, formal and informal proofs are _talking
about the same world_ and they _must play by the same rules_. *)
(** ** Informal Proofs by Induction *)
(** Since we've spent much of this chapter looking "under the hood" at
formal proofs by induction, now is a good moment to talk a little
about _informal_ proofs by induction.
In the real world of mathematical communication, written proofs
range from extremely longwinded and pedantic to extremely brief
and telegraphic. The ideal is somewhere in between, of course,
but while you are getting used to the style it is better to start
out at the pedantic end. Also, during the learning phase, it is
probably helpful to have a clear standard to compare against.
With this in mind, we offer two templates below -- one for proofs
by induction over _data_ (i.e., where the thing we're doing
induction on lives in [Type]) and one for proofs by induction over
_evidence_ (i.e., where the inductively defined thing lives in
[Prop]). In the rest of this course, please follow one of the two
for _all_ of your inductive proofs. *)
(** *** Induction Over an Inductively Defined Set *)
(** _Template_:
- _Theorem_: <Universally quantified proposition of the form
"For all [n:S], [P(n)]," where [S] is some inductively defined
set.>
_Proof_: By induction on [n].
<one case for each constructor [c] of [S]...>
- Suppose [n = c a1 ... ak], where <...and here we state
the IH for each of the [a]'s that has type [S], if any>.
We must show <...and here we restate [P(c a1 ... ak)]>.
<go on and prove [P(n)] to finish the case...>
- <other cases similarly...> []
_Example_:
- _Theorem_: For all sets [X], lists [l : list X], and numbers
[n], if [length l = n] then [index (S n) l = None].
_Proof_: By induction on [l].
- Suppose [l = []]. We must show, for all numbers [n],
that, if length [[] = n], then [index (S n) [] =
None].
This follows immediately from the definition of index.
- Suppose [l = x :: l'] for some [x] and [l'], where
[length l' = n'] implies [index (S n') l' = None], for
any number [n']. We must show, for all [n], that, if
[length (x::l') = n] then [index (S n) (x::l') =
None].
Let [n] be a number with [length l = n]. Since
length l = length (x::l') = S (length l'),
it suffices to show that
index (S (length l')) l' = None.
]]
But this follows directly from the induction hypothesis,
picking [n'] to be length [l']. [] *)
(** *** Induction Over an Inductively Defined Proposition *)
(** Since inductively defined proof objects are often called
"derivation trees," this form of proof is also known as _induction
on derivations_.
_Template_:
- _Theorem_: <Proposition of the form "[Q -> P]," where [Q] is
some inductively defined proposition (more generally,
"For all [x] [y] [z], [Q x y z -> P x y z]")>
_Proof_: By induction on a derivation of [Q]. <Or, more
generally, "Suppose we are given [x], [y], and [z]. We
show that [Q x y z] implies [P x y z], by induction on a
derivation of [Q x y z]"...>
<one case for each constructor [c] of [Q]...>
- Suppose the final rule used to show [Q] is [c]. Then
<...and here we state the types of all of the [a]'s
together with any equalities that follow from the
definition of the constructor and the IH for each of
the [a]'s that has type [Q], if there are any>. We must
show <...and here we restate [P]>.
<go on and prove [P] to finish the case...>
- <other cases similarly...> []
_Example_
- _Theorem_: The [<=] relation is transitive -- i.e., for all
numbers [n], [m], and [o], if [n <= m] and [m <= o], then
[n <= o].
_Proof_: By induction on a derivation of [m <= o].
- Suppose the final rule used to show [m <= o] is
[le_n]. Then [m = o] and we must show that [n <= m],
which is immediate by hypothesis.
- Suppose the final rule used to show [m <= o] is
[le_S]. Then [o = S o'] for some [o'] with [m <= o'].
We must show that [n <= S o'].
By induction hypothesis, [n <= o'].
But then, by [le_S], [n <= S o']. [] *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** * Optional Material *)
(** The remainder of this chapter offers some additional details on
how induction works in Coq, the process of building proof
trees, and the "trusted computing base" that underlies
Coq proofs. It can safely be skimmed on a first reading. (We
recommend skimming rather than skipping over it outright: it
answers some questions that occur to many Coq users at some point,
so it is useful to have a rough idea of what's here.) *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** ** Induction Principles in [Prop] *)
(** Earlier, we looked in detail at the induction principles that Coq
generates for inductively defined _sets_. The induction
principles for inductively defined _propositions_ like [gorgeous]
are a tiny bit more complicated. As with all induction
principles, we want to use the induction principle on [gorgeous]
to prove things by inductively considering the possible shapes
that something in [gorgeous] can have -- either it is evidence
that [0] is gorgeous, or it is evidence that, for some [n], [3+n]
is gorgeous, or it is evidence that, for some [n], [5+n] is
gorgeous and it includes evidence that [n] itself is. Intuitively
speaking, however, what we want to prove are not statements about
_evidence_ but statements about _numbers_. So we want an
induction principle that lets us prove properties of numbers by
induction on evidence.
For example, from what we've said so far, you might expect the
inductive definition of [gorgeous]...
Inductive gorgeous : nat -> Prop :=
g_0 : gorgeous 0
| g_plus3 : forall n, gorgeous n -> gorgeous (3+m)
| g_plus5 : forall n, gorgeous n -> gorgeous (5+m).
...to give rise to an induction principle that looks like this...
gorgeous_ind_max :
forall P : (forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> Prop),
P O g_0 ->
(forall (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e -> P (3+m) (g_plus3 m e) ->
(forall (m : nat) (e : gorgeous m),
P m e -> P (5+m) (g_plus5 m e) ->
forall (n : nat) (e : gorgeous n), P n e
... because:
- Since [gorgeous] is indexed by a number [n] (every [gorgeous]
object [e] is a piece of evidence that some particular number
[n] is gorgeous), the proposition [P] is parameterized by both
[n] and [e] -- that is, the induction principle can be used to
prove assertions involving both a gorgeous number and the
evidence that it is gorgeous.
- Since there are three ways of giving evidence of gorgeousness
([gorgeous] has three constructors), applying the induction
principle generates three subgoals:
- We must prove that [P] holds for [O] and [b_0].
- We must prove that, whenever [n] is a gorgeous
number and [e] is an evidence of its gorgeousness,
if [P] holds of [n] and [e],
then it also holds of [3+m] and [g_plus3 n e].
- We must prove that, whenever [n] is a gorgeous
number and [e] is an evidence of its gorgeousness,
if [P] holds of [n] and [e],
then it also holds of [5+m] and [g_plus5 n e].
- If these subgoals can be proved, then the induction principle
tells us that [P] is true for _all_ gorgeous numbers [n] and
evidence [e] of their gorgeousness.
But this is a little more flexibility than we actually need or
want: it is giving us a way to prove logical assertions where the
assertion involves properties of some piece of _evidence_ of
gorgeousness, while all we really care about is proving
properties of _numbers_ that are gorgeous -- we are interested in
assertions about numbers, not about evidence. It would therefore
be more convenient to have an induction principle for proving
propositions [P] that are parameterized just by [n] and whose
conclusion establishes [P] for all gorgeous numbers [n]:
forall P : nat -> Prop,
... ->
forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n
For this reason, Coq actually generates the following simplified
induction principle for [gorgeous]: *)
Check gorgeous_ind.
(* ===> gorgeous_ind
: forall P : nat -> Prop,
P 0 ->
(forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n -> P (3 + n)) ->
(forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n -> P (5 + n)) ->
forall n : nat, gorgeous n -> P n *)
(** In particular, Coq has dropped the evidence term [e] as a
parameter of the the proposition [P], and consequently has
rewritten the assumption [forall (n : nat) (e: gorgeous n), ...]
to be [forall (n : nat), gorgeous n -> ...]; i.e., we no longer
require explicit evidence of the provability of [gorgeous n]. *)
(** In English, [gorgeous_ind] says:
- Suppose, [P] is a property of natural numbers (that is, [P n] is
a [Prop] for every [n]). To show that [P n] holds whenever [n]
is gorgeous, it suffices to show:
- [P] holds for [0],
- for any [n], if [n] is gorgeous and [P] holds for
[n], then [P] holds for [3+n],
- for any [n], if [n] is gorgeous and [P] holds for
[n], then [P] holds for [5+n]. *)
(** As expected, we can apply [gorgeous_ind] directly instead of using [induction]. *)
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful' : forall n, gorgeous n -> beautiful n.
Proof.
intros.
apply gorgeous_ind.
Case "g_0".
apply b_0.
Case "g_plus3".
intros.
apply b_sum. apply b_3.
apply H1.
Case "g_plus5".
intros.
apply b_sum. apply b_5.
apply H1.
apply H.
Qed.
(** The precise form of an Inductive definition can affect the
induction principle Coq generates.
For example, in [Logic], we have defined [<=] as: *)
(* Inductive le : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| le_n : forall n, le n n
| le_S : forall n m, (le n m) -> (le n (S m)). *)
(** This definition can be streamlined a little by observing that the
left-hand argument [n] is the same everywhere in the definition,
so we can actually make it a "general parameter" to the whole
definition, rather than an argument to each constructor. *)
Inductive le (n:nat) : nat -> Prop :=
| le_n : le n n
| le_S : forall m, (le n m) -> (le n (S m)).
Notation "m <= n" := (le m n).
(** The second one is better, even though it looks less symmetric.
Why? Because it gives us a simpler induction principle. *)
Check le_ind.
(* ===> forall (n : nat) (P : nat -> Prop),
P n ->
(forall m : nat, n <= m -> P m -> P (S m)) ->
forall n0 : nat, n <= n0 -> P n0 *)
(** By contrast, the induction principle that Coq calculates for the
first definition has a lot of extra quantifiers, which makes it
messier to work with when proving things by induction. Here is
the induction principle for the first [le]: *)
(* le_ind :
forall P : nat -> nat -> Prop,
(forall n : nat, P n n) ->
(forall n m : nat, le n m -> P n m -> P n (S m)) ->
forall n n0 : nat, le n n0 -> P n n0 *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** * Additional Exercises *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (foo_ind_principle) *)
(** Suppose we make the following inductive definition:
Inductive foo (X : Set) (Y : Set) : Set :=
| foo1 : X -> foo X Y
| foo2 : Y -> foo X Y
| foo3 : foo X Y -> foo X Y.
Fill in the blanks to complete the induction principle that will be
generated by Coq.
foo_ind
: forall (X Y : Set) (P : foo X Y -> Prop),
(forall x : X, __________________________________) ->
(forall y : Y, __________________________________) ->
(________________________________________________) ->
________________________________________________
*)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (bar_ind_principle) *)
(** Consider the following induction principle:
bar_ind
: forall P : bar -> Prop,
(forall n : nat, P (bar1 n)) ->
(forall b : bar, P b -> P (bar2 b)) ->
(forall (b : bool) (b0 : bar), P b0 -> P (bar3 b b0)) ->
forall b : bar, P b
Write out the corresponding inductive set definition.
Inductive bar : Set :=
| bar1 : ________________________________________
| bar2 : ________________________________________
| bar3 : ________________________________________.
*)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (no_longer_than_ind) *)
(** Given the following inductively defined proposition:
Inductive no_longer_than (X : Set) : (list X) -> nat -> Prop :=
| nlt_nil : forall n, no_longer_than X [] n
| nlt_cons : forall x l n, no_longer_than X l n ->
no_longer_than X (x::l) (S n)
| nlt_succ : forall l n, no_longer_than X l n ->
no_longer_than X l (S n).
write the induction principle generated by Coq.
no_longer_than_ind
: forall (X : Set) (P : list X -> nat -> Prop),
(forall n : nat, ____________________) ->
(forall (x : X) (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n -> ____________________ ->
_____________________________ ->
(forall (l : list X) (n : nat),
no_longer_than X l n -> ____________________ ->
_____________________________ ->
forall (l : list X) (n : nat), no_longer_than X l n ->
____________________
*)
(** [] *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** ** Induction Principles for other Logical Propositions *)
(** Similarly, in [Logic] we have defined [eq] as: *)
(* Inductive eq (X:Type) : X -> X -> Prop :=
refl_equal : forall x, eq X x x. *)
(** In the Coq standard library, the definition of equality is
slightly different: *)
Inductive eq' (X:Type) (x:X) : X -> Prop :=
refl_equal' : eq' X x x.
(** The advantage of this definition is that the induction
principle that Coq derives for it is precisely the familiar
principle of _Leibniz equality_: what we mean when we say "[x] and
[y] are equal" is that every property on [P] that is true of [x]
is also true of [y]. *)
Check eq'_ind.
(* ===>
forall (X : Type) (x : X) (P : X -> Prop),
P x -> forall y : X, x =' y -> P y
===> (i.e., after a little reorganization)
forall (X : Type) (x : X) forall y : X,
x =' y ->
forall P : X -> Prop, P x -> P y *)
(** The induction principles for conjunction and disjunction are a
good illustration of Coq's way of generating simplified induction
principles for [Inductive]ly defined propositions, which we
discussed above. You try first: *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (and_ind_principle) *)
(** See if you can predict the induction principle for conjunction. *)
(* Check and_ind. *)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (or_ind_principle) *)
(** See if you can predict the induction principle for disjunction. *)
(* Check or_ind. *)
(** [] *)
Check and_ind.
(** From the inductive definition of the proposition [and P Q]
Inductive and (P Q : Prop) : Prop :=
conj : P -> Q -> (and P Q).
we might expect Coq to generate this induction principle
and_ind_max :
forall (P Q : Prop) (P0 : P /\ Q -> Prop),
(forall (a : P) (b : Q), P0 (conj P Q a b)) ->
forall a : P /\ Q, P0 a
but actually it generates this simpler and more useful one:
and_ind :
forall P Q P0 : Prop,
(P -> Q -> P0) ->
P /\ Q -> P0
In the same way, when given the inductive definition of [or P Q]
Inductive or (P Q : Prop) : Prop :=
| or_introl : P -> or P Q
| or_intror : Q -> or P Q.
instead of the "maximal induction principle"
or_ind_max :
forall (P Q : Prop) (P0 : P \/ Q -> Prop),
(forall a : P, P0 (or_introl P Q a)) ->
(forall b : Q, P0 (or_intror P Q b)) ->
forall o : P \/ Q, P0 o
what Coq actually generates is this:
or_ind :
forall P Q P0 : Prop,
(P -> P0) ->
(Q -> P0) ->
P \/ Q -> P0
]]
*)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (False_ind_principle) *)
(** Can you predict the induction principle for falsehood? *)
(* Check False_ind. *)
(** [] *)
(** Here's the induction principle that Coq generates for existentials: *)
Check ex_ind.
(* ===> forall (X:Type) (P: X->Prop) (Q: Prop),
(forall witness:X, P witness -> Q) ->
ex X P ->
Q *)
(** This induction principle can be understood as follows: If we have
a function [f] that can construct evidence for [Q] given _any_
witness of type [X] together with evidence that this witness has
property [P], then from a proof of [ex X P] we can extract the
witness and evidence that must have been supplied to the
constructor, give these to [f], and thus obtain a proof of [Q]. *)
(* ######################################################### *)
(** ** Explicit Proof Objects for Induction *)
(** Although tactic-based proofs are normally much easier to
work with, the ability to write a proof term directly is sometimes
very handy, particularly when we want Coq to do something slightly
non-standard. *)
(** Recall the induction principle on naturals that Coq generates for
us automatically from the Inductive declation for [nat]. *)